A Response to Wendy McElroy on Abortion and Retroactive Justice

Wendy McElroy opens her article On Abortion with this paragraph:

When I was eighteen, I chose to have an abortion. Accordingly, the question I am addressing here is nothing less than whether I have committed murder. If the fetus is a human being with individual rights, then I am among millions of women who have committed first degree, premeditated murder, and I should be subject to whatever penalties are imposed upon that crime. The fact that I did not know I was killing a human being is irrelevant, just as the state of knowledge of a racist who kills blacks while believing them to be animals is irrelevant to the fact that he has committed murder. If you shy away from such prosecution, you are shying away from the antiabortionist position.

McElroy makes numerous arguments about abortion that I disagree with, but here I want to focus on her argument that being against abortion logically entails advocating prosecution of millions of women for having previously committed the crime of murder. What she is saying is that if you want to oppose abortion on the principled grounds that it is an act of aggression, you must accept that you are advocating imprisoning millions of women for past abortions. Failure to acknowledge this, according to McElroy, is to be inconsistent or to obscure the implications of one's argument.

This is simply false. McElroy is conflating two entirely separate problems:

  1. What are the correct principles that should be law in a libertarian legal order?
  2. Once a libertarian law is established, how does one address justice or accountability for past wrongdoing?

McElroy assumes that you can only recognise a libertarian law if you are also advocating that it be retroactively applied. The abolitionists certainly did not think that way about slavery. They focussed on making slavery illegal and there was no push for ex post facto justice against former slaveholders. Ex post facto laws are prohibited by the U.S. Constitution and in many other countries, in line with Enlightenment legal principles.

Libertarians hold that the State is a criminal organisation based on theft. This implies that all the people who work for the State are part of a criminal gang. However, this does not mean that all current government employees would have to go to prison if a libertarian legal order were established. Some kind of retroactive punishment might be justified in some cases, but it is not a given. Getting the law right and accounting for past injustices are two distinct problems.

When it comes to outlawing abortion, there are many reasons for libertarians to argue that such a law should not be applied retroactively, especially since so many people do not yet understand or accept that abortion is wrong. The message of the current law is that abortion is a blameless act. Public education, the media, and most intellectuals (including libertarians) endorse abortion. Establishing a law against abortion would require a complete change in societal norms. Under these circumstances, it is not at all clear that retroactive punishment would be justified.

So, no, I can argue that abortion is homicide without arguing that Wendy McElroy has to go to prison because she had an abortion when she was 18. Just like the abolitionists, I can argue that it is time to recognise a crime without advocating retroactive punishment for what happened in the past.

Having dealt with the argument about retroactive justice, there is another implication in McElroy's statement. I think McElroy is emphasising that the very idea that millions of regular women have committed homicide seems alien and outlandish to her.

Yet the reality is even more shocking. McElroy only talks about women, but seeing abortion as a violation of the nonaggression principle implies that millions of men, too, have been accomplices or direct causal agents in homicide. After all, the men were also parents with responsibility for the child. If the men did not object or try to prevent the abortion, they were complicit in the crime. And beyond just complicity, no doubt countless of those men were in fact the ones pushing the women to get the abortion, so they were the instigators of the crime.

Indeed, this does all seem like a very hard pill to swallow. To recognise abortion as a violation of the nonaggression principle implies that approximately a fifth of the population has committed homicide against the most defenceless and innocent human beings of all. Even if those mothers and fathers who had aborted their child before a law against abortion was established understood that there would be no retroactive justice against them, they would still have to come to terms with the reality of what they have done.

Parental Obligations Stem from Causal Action, Not Mere Biology

One theory of parental obligations holds that the biological relatedness of parent to child is the basis for parental obligations. This view holds that parents have enforceable positive obligations simply because they are biological parents. In his article Abortion and Parental Obligation, Andrew J. Peach makes this argument citing Stephen Schwarz's book The Moral Question of Abortion:

Following Schwarz, then, I will be defending the theses that the being in the womb is a person from conception and that, contrary to Thomson, parents simply by virtue of the biological relationship do have a special responsibility to this being. Although voluntary sexual intercourse is the means by which virtually all conception takes place, Schwarz is arguing that it is the biological bond between parents and children itself that grounds the obligation. In other words, the act of sexual intercourse is not in itself the ground of the obligation; it is merely the act that brought about the existence of the child who is biologically connected to the parents. So, it is not so much the choice to have sex that obligates a couple as it is the reality, the relationship, that is brought about by that choice.

Peach argues in a footnote that a “biological bond” exists "between the parents as the natural authors of the child—their sperm and egg that unite to form this new human being," and that this bond "is really the crucial one for determining parental obligation."

This is not quite right. Parental obligation arises from the voluntary act of making one's gametes available for fertilization—whether through sexual intercourse, which entails the inherent possibility of fertilization, or through assisted reproductive technologies such as IVF. In both cases, the gamete providers bear ultimate causal responsibility for the creation of a child in a state of peril. Therefore, both the mother and father are causally obligated to remove the child from the state of peril by raising him to the safety of adulthood.

James Lindemann Nelson explains why this act creates causal obligation:

The making available of one's gametes is an act highly proximate to conception, and, in concert with the other parent's actions, is jointly sufficient for it. Our practice is generally to take proximity and sufficiency pretty seriously; a pair of coordinated actions which were proximate to and jointly sufficient for some event, and were not the result of forcing or fraudulent action on the part of others would be hard not to see as the cause of the event in question. Becoming a parent generally fits this model.

Peach is correct that it is not merely the act of sex that creates obligation, but he is mistaken in attributing the obligation to biology alone. It is action that creates parental obligations. Sex involves the act of making one's gametes available for fertilization. Obligation comes from the reasonably foreseeable consequences of this act.

Does a rape victim have parental obligations?

The huge difference between the causal theory and the biological theory is in the question of parental obligations for rape victims. Peach acknowledges an important logical implication of the biological theory:

If the biological bond is the true ground of parental obligations, then women who are raped also have maternal obligations because, as a point of fact, they are mothers; the same biological bond exists between the woman and child in the case of rape as exists between a woman and child of a voluntary conception. As Schwarz explains in regard to the woman who has conceived due to rape: “The child is her child; this remains true even when the child is conceived in violent intercourse and forced on her. The reality of the child as a person, and as entrusted to the woman as her mother, remains fully intact. The woman may not get rid of the child if this means child neglect, still less if it means killing, as in abortion.”

There is a lot to unpack here. Firstly, there are two arguments at stake:

  1. Does a rape victim have parental obligations?
  2. Is abortion justified in cases of rape?

Since Peach and Schwarz are concerned to argue against abortion, they both address these two questions only in connection with each other. But these are two independent questions.

Addressing the first question, unlike the biological theory, the causal theory of parental obligations does not imply that a rape victim has parental obligations. A rape victim did not act to make her gametes available for fertilization; she was coerced into doing so by an invasive act of aggression. Therefore, a rape victim does not have parental obligations to any resultant child.

The case of rape highlights the absence of a compelling argument for the biological theory of obligation. Why should biology alone impose parental obligations in cases of rape? Schwarz and Peach argue that the resulting child is "entrusted to the woman as its mother." The passive voice in "entrusted" leaves unclear who is doing the entrusting. Is it anyone in particular, or society at large, or God? It seems likely that they are making a religious argument.

It is true that abortion is incompatible with parental obligations in cases of consensual sex, but not in cases of rape. However, although a rape victim does not have parental obligations, it does not necessarily follow that abortion is justified in such cases. Peach and Schwarz could argue that abortion is not legitimate in such cases on other grounds. In trying to argue that it is parental obligation which makes abortion impermissible in cases of rape, they are forced to rely on a biological theory of obligation that ultimately lacks any philosophical justification.

Children Do Not Have Obligations to Their Parents

Recently when I presented the argument that parents have enforceable positive obligations to their children, someone asked whether children have similar obligations to their parents. Do parents have an enforceable claim against their children according to a libertarian legal order?

The short answer is no. Children owe their parents the negative obligation not to initiate aggression against them, just as they owe this to all others. They do not owe their parents any positive obligations, such as the provision of care in their parents' old age.

There are no legitimate unchosen positive obligations. Legitimate obligations only arise as a result of one's actions. One must also accept as "chosen” those obligations that come from the unintended but reasonably foreseeable consequences of one's actions. This responsibility for the consequences of one's actions is the basis of the positive obligations that parents have to their children.

However, a child has not acted in any way that gives rise to positive obligations to his parents. Children are brought into life without action on their part. The actions that created a child were undertaken by his parents. Children do not (and cannot) consent to their relationship with their parents. That relationship is something that is put upon them without agreement. Therefore, there are no grounds for parents to have any claim against their children for positive obligations.

Those that argue children have obligations to their parents must argue that there are legitimate unchosen positive obligations. Here is an example of the argument from Andrew J. Peach:

it is generally acknowledged that relationships and circumstances give rise to obligations that are quite independent of the wishes of the people involved in those relationships and circumstances. For example, children (simply in virtue of being children) have special responsibilities toward their parents, especially during the latter’s twilight years. Children who do not make special allowances for their elderly parents, by providing emotional, financial, or physical support or just being generally solicitous of their well-being, are as unjust as they are ungrateful.

Peach is correct that people can have obligations "independent of [their] wishes", but there is something missing in his account. One cannot acquire positive obligations independent of one's actions. A father who does not wish to have the responsibility of being a parent still has a rightful obligation to his child because of the father's actions. He had sex, which is an act that has the reasonably foreseeable risk of creating a child, even when that was unintended. However, that same man does not have a legitimate obligation towards children that he did not father, since he did not act in any way that would lead to such an obligation.

Peach does not justify the unchosen obligations, he just takes it as given ("generally acknowledged") that they exist. That's because there is no logical basis for justifying such obligations.

I wonder if those who think children have positive obligations to their parents argue that such obligations are enforceable. Should parents be able to use the law to make their children pay for their care in old age? What could possibly be the basis to justify such a claim?

Here's another question: if parents had been negligent or abusive to their children, would the children still owe them obligations? Of course, parents are obliged to look after their kids no matter how badly their kids behave towards them because that obligation results from the parents own actions. But I wonder if those who think that children have an obligation to their parents would also argue that such obligations are independent of how badly the parents treated the kids?

The only answer that makes sense of all this to me is that children do not have positive obligations to their parents. I wrote more about this topic in my response to Harry Browne's letter to his daughter.

Defence of Abortion Entails Defence of Infanticide

All arguments used to justify abortion also logically justify infanticide. Pro-abortion arguments such as that rights are acquired rather than inherent, as well as the numerous criteria that have been suggested to qualify for rights (such as achieving a level of rationality or certain physiological characteristics), all apply just as equally to newborn infanticide as they do to abortion.

This means that a defence of abortion logically entails a defence of infanticide. You cannot choose to defend abortion and not defend infanticide without contradiction. This is a matter of fact that influential pro-abortion philosophers explicitly accept. Here are some examples.

In Practical Ethics (1979), Peter Singer readily admits to the logical connection between arguments for abortion and infanticide:

liberals usually hold that it is permissible to kill an embryo or fetus but not a baby. I have argued that the life of a fetus (and even more plainly, of an embryo) is of no greater value than the life of a nonhuman animal at a similar level of rationality, self-awareness, capacity to feel and so on, and that because no fetus is a person, no fetus has the same claim to life as a person. Now we have to face the fact that these arguments apply to the newborn baby as much as to the fetus. A week-old baby is not a rational and self-aware being, and there are many nonhuman animals whose rationality, self-awareness, capacity to feel and so on, exceed that of a human baby a week or a month old. If, for the reasons I have given, the fetus does not have the same claim to life as a person, it appears that the newborn baby does not either. Thus, although my position on the status of fetal life may be acceptable to many, the implications of this position for the status of newborn life are at odds with the virtually unchallenged assumption that the life of a newborn baby is as sacrosanct as that of an adult… I do not regard the conflict between the position I have taken and widely accepted views about the sanctity of infant life as a ground for abandoning my position.

In Abortion and Infanticide (1983), Philosopher Michael Tooley acknowledges that pro-choice arguments are pro-infanticide arguments and he knows that this is a "difficult issue" to accept:

Most current discussions of abortion tend to treat it in isolation from the question of the morality of  infanticide. One of the central contentions to be advanced here is that it is very difficult indeed to arrive at a defensible position on abortion unless one is prepared to come to terms with the difficult issue of the moral status of infanticide.

David Boonin's 1998 book A Defense of Abortion evaluates various arguments in terms of how "attractive" they are to those wanting to defeat rights-based arguments against abortion. Having rejected one suggestion, he considers whether to defend abortion by defending infanticide, but decides that this is not "attractive" since to acknowledge that abortion is on a par with infanticide would delegitimise it:

A defender of abortion …. could agree that you and I have a right to life but deny that newborn infants do. If newborn infants do not have a right to life, then it will again be a simple matter to establish that fetuses lack such a right, and the rights-based argument against abortion will again be defeated. This suggestion is likely to strike most readers as hardly more attractive than the first. In the popular debate about abortion, at least, to say that abortion is morally on a par with killing newborn babies is simply to say that abortion is morally impermissible.

Having accepted that abortion may be on a par with infanticide and that, if so, this would lead many to consider abortion unjustifiable, Boonin chooses to simply ignore this problem without providing any defence or argument:

A number of philosophers, including such prominent figures as Peter Singer and Michael Tooley, have argued that human infants do not have a right to life. And these arguments deserve to be taken seriously on their own terms. But they need not be taken seriously here. For the purposes of this book, arguments for the claim that human infants do not have a right to life can simply be set aside.

Whereas Singer and Tooley at least accepted the logical consequences of their pro-abortion arguments openly, Boonin is less honest. He chooses to "set aside" those logical consequences of his argument that he knows many will find horrific.

The Inconsistency of Pro-Abortion Libertarians

A few oddballs calling themselves libertarians have openly argued for both a pro- abortion and pro-infanticide position. In his 1895 article L'Enfant Terrible, Benjamin Tucker accepted that if one considers abortion justified then one also considers killing a newborn infant justified:

If, then, the child is the mother's while in the womb, by what consideration does the title to it become vested in another than the mother on its emergence from the womb and pending the day of its emancipation? I think that no valid consideration can be shown; and if such is the case, then it is established that the unemancipated child is the property of its mother, of which, by an obvious corollary, she may dispose as freely as she may dispose of any other property belonging to her.

In a 2019 article Abortion and Infanticide a Triple Libertarian and Critical-Rationalist Defence, Jan Lester argues for "the moral permissibility of the abortion and infanticide of unwanted humans" and states that "abortion and infanticide are, in themselves, morally neutral". Although the mind boggles at how anyone can evince such a profound level of moral bankrupcy, he is nonetheless correct when he states that the two positions are inseparable:

It is common, however, for people to accept some versions of these arguments as applied to abortion but reject them as regards infanticide. And that is simply to be logically inconsistent.

Yet this is not the usual stance of pro-choice libertarians. Most libertarian defenders of abortion want to hold the untenable position that abortion is valid but infanticide is not. A common way of attempting to square this circle is to argue that a baby in utero is some kind of aggressor by way of trespass, but this position relies on an unjustifiable denial of causal parental responsibility.

Libertarians who have attempted justifications of this kind include Murray Rothbard, Williamson Evers, and Walter Block. Rothbard's determination to deny causal parental obligations led him to argue the odd position that infanticide is justified if by deliberate starvation but not if by physical assault.

Most other pro-abortion libertarians fail to grapple with the logical implication of their view when it comes to infanticide. Unlike Benjamin Tucker and Jan Lester who say the quiet part out loud– openly advocating infanticide– pro-abortion libertarians usually either ignore their own inconsistency by not talking about infanticide or declare arbitrarily that they do not support it (despite supporting abortion).

If you are pro-abortion, at least have the honesty to accept the logical consequence: all your arguments for abortion also justify infanticide.

Opposing Parental Authority As A Strategy To Increase State Control Of Children

Parents can and do abuse their authority over their children. Children have rights and should not be aggressed against, neglected, or denied the care and support from parents that they have a legitimate claim to. However, those who argue for children's rights do not always have the interests of the children in mind. Sometimes the advocacy of children's rights is a vehicle for promoting the interests of political authority.

As discussed in previous posts, one school of thought in philosophy of the family holds that the State is the rightful owner of children and that parents are a barrier to State power.

Those who see parents as a barrier to State power seek strategies to separate parents from children. One example is to advocate for communal child rearing. A related strategy is to seek ways to weaken parental authority.

In What's Wrong With Children's Rights, Martin Guggenheim identified two distinct goals within the children's rights movement of the 1960s:

Broadly speaking, the children’s rights movement since the 1960s has focused on two sometimes intertwined but often completely separate matters. One concerns the rights of children with respect to the exercise of state power; the other, the rights of children with respect to the exercise of parental authority.

Guggenheim argues that the goal of reducing state power over children was rapidly sidelined. Instead, reducing parental authority over children became the dominant goal. A key group driving the movement was lawyers involved in the emerging field of children's rights law. Guggenheim was himself a children's rights lawyer and he laments the fact that the movement came to focus almost exclusively on the reduction of parental authority as opposed to the reduction of state power.

In Parental Rights the Contemporary Assault on Traditional Liberties, Krason and D'Agostino argue that children's rights advocates use the existence of abuse as a pretext to justify the State taking authority over children instead of parents:

Some of the most influential advocates of children’s rights begin with observations that some parents are not protecting their children. Then they use instances of child abuse to justify a general transfer of authority from the parents to social workers and lawyers.

As an example, they cite Cohen's argument in Equal Rights for Children that the existence of child abuse justifies restructuring of all relationships between parents and children:

we must be ready to accept the idea that dealing with child abuse will mean changing the structures of all relationships between adults and children—not merely the bad ones. If we can not say in advance which adults are likely to abuse children and which are not, then we can not reduce child abuse by treating parental problems case by case. We would be too late—and probably do too little as well. To treat the problem seriously, then, we would have to find a way to build checks against child abuse into all our relationships with children.

This opposition to parental authority is characteristic of all Statists who see parents as a barrier to political authority. From the early Progressive movement, parents were seen as a problem that children need to be liberated from. In The Home: Its Work and Influence (1903), Charlotte Perkins Gilman argued for recognition of children's rights as a way for the State to gain more influence over them and the parents less:

There is no more brilliant hope on earth today, than this new thought about the child .… the recognition of 'the child,' children as a class, children as citizens with rights to be guaranteed only by the state; instead of our previous attitude toward them of absolute personal ownership—the unchecked tyranny, or as unchecked indulgence, of the private home.

Many intellectuals have made the argument that only people approved by political authority ought to have the right to parent children, and that unapproved should never be left with parental authority. This is set out as a policy goal of licensing of parents, or restricting of parenting to only those approved by the State. One of the anthropologist Margaret Mead's proposals was that children be taken from natural parents and assigned to couples specially trained and certified for parenthood. This idea was also advocated by Alvin Toffler in Future Shock (1970) and by the academic Hugh LaFollette in his 1980 paper Licencing Parents. LaFollette argued that if any unlicensed parents have unapproved children then the State should "remove the children and put them up for adoption.”

Communal Child Rearing As A Strategy To Separate Parents From Children

In a previous post I outlined three schools of thought on the relationship between parents and political authority. One of those schools of thought sees parents as a rival power base to political authority that must be overcome. This is the perspective of communist and leftist movements that view the influence of parents on their children as a barrier to State power.

This group sees children as property of the State. By separating parents from their children, parents can be more easily controlled and children more easily indoctrinated by the State. One strategy of those who want to separate parents from children is to advocate communal child rearing.

The earliest advocate of communal child rearing was Plato, who set this out in The Republic. Plato wanted the State to become the central focus of commitment instead of the family, possibly influenced by the example of Sparta using this policy for the same goal.

The abolition of the family has been an explicit goal of all communist movements and is stated in The Communist Manifesto by Marx and Engels (1848). It was also advocated by pre-Marxist communists such as Morelly in his La Code de la Nature, (1755). Although Rousseau did not call for full communal child rearing, his critique of the family led many that he influenced, such as Morelly, to see this as a solution.

The goal of abolishing the family was advocated by Shulamith Firestone in The Dialectic of Sex (1970) and by various others since as a perennial aim of radical leftist movements. What the abstract goal of "abolishing the family" means in terms of specific policy is compulsory separation of children from their parents and raising of children in communal groups organised by the State.

Anthropologist Margaret Mead argued for removing the children from parents as part of her critique of the nuclear family. She presented a positive depiction of Samoa where she argued that the "large family community" of communal child-rearing "diffuses" affection and prevents the formation of the "crippling attitudes which have been labelled Oedipus complexes, Electra complexes, and so on". Mead's goal was "to mitigate… the strong role which parents play in children's lives."

Contemporary philosophers Brighouse & Swift advocated breaking the relationship between biological parents and their children in pursuit of egalitarianism. Rather than specifically advocating communal child rearing, they make a more general argument against the view that children should be raised by their biological parents. They argue that "adults have no fundamental right to parent their own biological children". They see being a parent as a benefit that should ideally be distributed in a more egalitarian way, so they argue that non-parents such as homosexuals, single people, and polyamorous groups should have access to children to experience the benefit of raising kids too. They argue that the claim children have a right to be raised by their biological parents should be opposed as prejudice.

Moderate leftists such as Brighouse & Swift advocate incrementally more separation of children from their biological parents, whereas radicals such as Marx want total abolition of the family.

There may be other motivations for the advocacy of communal child rearing, but for some it is a conscious strategy to separate parents from their children and thereby attack the family as rival power base to the State.

A Response To Kerry Baldwin on Fetal Self Ownership

Whilst doing research for a forthcoming book about libertarianism and parental obligations, I was interested to come across the work of Kerry Baldwin. This post is a response to the ideas that Baldwin put forward in her two-part podcast series on libertarianism, abortion, and fetal self-ownership as well as her debate with Walter Block on evictionism.

Abortion

On this blog, I have written about how support for abortion has corrupted libertarian theory. Baldwin makes an excellent point in this regard. She argues that the belief that abortion is legitimate undermines the principle of self ownership. The logical implication of assuming that abortion is valid is that individuals only have rights if their mother decides to grant them rights. As Baldwin puts it, this is not a theory of self ownership, it is a theory of "matriarchy".

In a recent post, I argued that the theory of acquired rights violates Hoppe's specificity principle. Although she used different terms and argued it a little differently, Baldwin made a very similar point in her series on fetal self ownership.

In her debate with Walter Block, Baldwin made an important objection to Block's evictionism. She pointed out that Block's characterisation of abortion as "eviction plus killing" is not accurate. As she noted, in fact most abortions are a process comprised of "killing plus removal of a dead body". This objection applies to Judith Jarvis Thomson's defence of abortion too, which also relies on the idea that abortion is legitimate because it can be categorised as an example of letting die not killing.

If Block is concerned to allow eviction but deny killing as he says, the logical consequence would be for him to argue that only extractive abortions (for example, hysterotomy) are legitimate and all non-extractive abortions are illegitimate according to evictionism. Extractive abortions are arguably examples of letting die, not killing, which is central to Block's justification. Yet Block seems entirely uninterested in such details. He provided no defence to Baldwin's objection in the debate, saying "I don't know as much about this as she does so I defer to what she said".

Parental Obligations

Baldwin is one of the few libertarians who argue that parents do have enforceable obligations towards their children as a result of their own causal actions. She argues that since pregnancy is a known possible outcome of consensual sex, parents have responsibility for the consequences of their actions and therefore they have obligations towards the child. This argument is of great interest to me, since I believe that among the competing libertarian views about parental obligations, only the principle of causal responsibility is correct. It seems that Baldwin might accept this principle.

However, Baldwin seems to have a much narrower definition of parental obligations. If I understand her correctly, she holds that a mother has the obligation to provide life support (gestation) during the period of non-viability of a fetus, and if the baby is unwanted then the mother also has the obligation to find a suitable caregiver once the baby is born.

If parents have an obligation to their children because they have responsibility for the consequences of their actions (in cases of consensual sex), then the obligation is far greater than Baldwin seems to accept. Children have a rightful claim against their parents not only for life support during pregnancy (as Baldwin argues), but also for whatever else is necessary to get the child out of peril and to a position of safety and self-sufficiency. This involves raising the child (and all that this entails) to the independence and self-sufficiency of adulthood.

According to this principle, parental obligations apply to both the mother and the father and both are jointly and severally liable towards the child, since both are responsible for putting the child in a state of peril as a result of creating the child. Baldwin makes the case for some limited enforceable obligations of the mother, but it is not clear to me whether she thinks that fathers have enforceable parental obligations or what these are.

Baldwin argues that it is a legitimate choice to give up a child for adoption. She emphasises that "there are many good reasons for not wanting to have a child". There are some cases in which parents do not have obligations, such as pregnancy resulting from rape. However, apart from those exceptions, you cannot legitimately give up parental obligations.

Parents who place a child in peril have a tort liability until that child is out of peril. Adoption is at best a delegation of this obligation, but even then the parents can never fully rid themselves of the legitimate claim that the child has on them (since it is not their claim to give up or nullify). It may be beneficial to support the institution of adoption for purely pragmatic reasons (making the best of a bad situation). Even if adoption should be supported for the sake of children, it is not a legitimate choice for the parents in terms of libertarian theory.

Finally, Baldwin seems to argue that the nature of pregnancy is significant for the role of women within libertarian theory, although it is not clear to me exactly what her argument is. She likens pregnancy to an act of production, with the mothers being "the producers of new self owners". Perhaps she is advocating some form of the theory of gestationalism (the idea that gestation is the primary basis for parental rights and obligations). This idea is not compatible with her support for children as self owners from conception because the unborn self owner already exists during gestation. Gestation is not an act of production since it does not contribute to the existence of the child. Rather, gestation is the first form of nurturing for an already existent unborn child that is developing. This idea of the mother as the "producer" is therefore incompatible with inherent self ownership.

Although I have outlined some disagreements, Baldwin is one of the few libertarians making philosophical arguments for inherent rights and for parental obligations and I appreciate her work.